34 found
Order:
Disambiguations
Sean D. Kelly [23]Sean Dorrance Kelly [11]
  1. Seeing things in Merleau-ponty.Sean D. Kelly - 2005 - In Taylor Carman (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Merleau-Ponty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 74-110.
    The passage above comes from the opening pages of Merleau-Ponty’s essay on Edmund Husserl. It proposes a risky interpretive principle. The main feature of this principle is that the seminal aspects of a thinker’s work are so close to him that he is incapable of articulating them himself. Nevertheless, these aspects pervade the work, give it its style, its sense and its direction, and therefore belong to it essentially. As Martin Heidegger writes, in a passage quoted by Merleau-Ponty: " The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  2. The non-conceptual content of perceptual experience: Situation dependence and fineness of grain.Sean D. Kelly - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):601-608.
    I begin by examining a recent debate between John McDowell and Christopher Peacocke over whether the content of perceptual experience is non-conceptual. Although I am sympathetic to Peacocke’s claim that perceptual content is non-conceptual, I suggest a number of ways in which his arguments fail to make that case. This failure stems from an over-emphasis on the "fine-grainedness" of perceptual content - a feature that is relatively unimportant to its non-conceptual structure. I go on to describe two other features of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  3. Demonstrative concepts and experience.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):397-420.
    A number of authors have argued recently that the content of perceptual experience can, and even must, be characterized in conceptual terms. Their claim, more precisely, is that every perceptual experience is such that, of necessity, its content is constituted entirely by concepts possessed by the subject having the experience. This is a surprising result. For it seems reasonable to think that a subject’s experiences could be richer and more fine-grained than his conceptual repertoire; that a subject might be able, (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  4. The puzzle of temporal experience.Sean D. Kelly - 2005 - In Andrew Brook (ed.), Cognition and the Brain: The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 208--238.
    There you are at the opera house. The soprano has just hit her high note – a glassshattering high C that fills the hall – and she holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds it. She holds the note for such a long time that after a while a funny thing happens: you no longer seem only to hear it, the note as it is currently sounding, that glass-shattering high C that is loud and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  5.  30
    Demonstrative Concepts and Experience.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (3):397-420.
    A number of authors have argued recently that the content of perceptual experience can, and even must, be characterized in conceptual terms. Their claim, more precisely, is that every perceptual experience is such that, of necessity, its content is constituted entirely by concepts possessed by the subject having the experience. This is a surprising result. For it seems reasonable to think that a subject’s experiences could be richer and more fine-grained than his conceptual repertoire; that a subject might be able, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  6. Merleau–ponty on the body.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2002 - Ratio 15 (4):376–391.
    The French philosopher Maurice Merleau-Ponty claims that there are two distinct ways in which we can understand the place of an object when we are visually apprehending it. The first involves an intentional relation to the object that is essentially cognitive or can serve as the input to cognitive processes; the second irreducibly involves a bodily set or preparation to deal with the object. Because of its essential bodily component, Merleau-Ponty calls this second kind of understanding ‘motor intentional’. In this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  7.  19
    Merleau–Ponty on the Body.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2002 - Ratio 15 (4):376-391.
    The French philosopher Maurice Merleau–Ponty claims that there are two distinct ways in which we can understand the place of an object when we are visually apprehending it. The first involves an intentional relation to the object that is essentially cognitive or can serve as the input to cognitive processes; the second irreducibly involves a bodily set or preparation to deal with the object. Because of its essential bodily component, Merleau–Ponty calls this second kind of understanding ‘motor intentional’. In this (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  8. The normative nature of perceptual experience.Sean D. Kelly - 2010 - In Bence Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the World. Oxford University Press. pp. 146.
  9. Grasping at straws: Motor intentionality and the cognitive science of skillful action.Sean D. Kelly - 2000 - In Essays in Honor of Hubert Dreyfus, Vol. II. MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  10.  36
    Content and Constancy: phenomenology, psychology, and the content of perception.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3):682-690.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  11. Closing the Gap: Phenomenology and Logical Analysis.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2005 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 13 (2):4-24.
    phenomenology and logical analysis. John Searle and Bert Dreyfus are for me two of the paradigm figures of contemporary philosophy, so I am extremely proud to have been offered the opportunity to engage with their work. The editors of The Harvard Review of Philosophy, it seems to me, have shown a keen sense of what is deep and important in our discipline by publishing extended interviews with these two influential thinkers. At the same time, writing this article meant entering into (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  12. Can one act for a reason without acting intentionally?Joshua Knobe & Sean D. Kelly - 2009 - In Constantine Sandis (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of Action. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 169--183.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  13. Temporal awareness.Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2005 - In David Woodruff Smith & Amie L. Thomasson (eds.), Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  14. Saving the Sacred from the Axial Revolution.Sean Dorrance Kelly & Hubert Dreyfus - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (2):195-203.
    Prominent defenders of the Enlightenment, like Jürgen Habermas, are beginning to recognize that the characterization of human beings in entirely rational and secular terms leaves out something important. Religion, they admit, plays an important role in human existence. But the return to a traditional monotheistic religion seems sociologically difficult after the death of God. We argue that Homeric polytheism retains a phenomenologically rich account of the sacred, and a similarly rich understanding of human existence in its midst. By opening ourselves (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15. The normative nature of perceptual experience.Sean D. Kelly - 2010 - In Bence Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the world. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16. What do we see (when we do)?Sean D. Kelly - 1999 - In Thomas Baldwin (ed.), Philosophical Topics. Routledge. pp. 107-128.
    1. The philosophical problem of what we see My topic revolves around what is apparently a very basic question. Stripped of all additions and in its leanest, most economical form, this is the question: "What do we see?" But in this most basic form the question admits of at least three different interpretations. In the first place, one might understand it to be an epistemological question, perhaps one with skeptical overtones. "What do we see?", on this reading, is short for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17. Perceptual Normativity and Human Freedom.Sean Dorrance Kelly - manuscript
  18.  98
    Phenomenology, dynamical neural networks and brain function.Donald Borrett, Sean D. Kelly & Hon Kwan - 2000 - Philosophical Psychology 13 (2):213-228.
    Current cognitive science models of perception and action assume that the objects that we move toward and perceive are represented as determinate in our experience of them. A proper phenomenology of perception and action, however, shows that we experience objects indeterminately when we are perceiving them or moving toward them. This indeterminacy, as it relates to simple movement and perception, is captured in the proposed phenomenologically based recurrent network models of brain function. These models provide a possible foundation from which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19. Heterophenomenology: Heavy-handed Sleight-of-hand. [REVIEW]Hubert Dreyfus & Sean D. Kelly - 2007 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 (1-2):45-55.
    We argue that heterophenomenology both over- and under-populates the intentional realm. For example, when one is involved in coping, one’s mind does not contain beliefs. Since the heterophenomenologist interprets all intentional commitment as belief, he necessarily overgenerates the belief contents of the mind. Since beliefs cannot capture the normative aspect of coping and perceiving, any method, such as heterophenomenology, that allows for only beliefs is guaranteed not only to overgenerate beliefs but also to undergenerate other kinds of intentional phenomena.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  20. A moment to reflect upon perceptual synchrony.Sean D. Kelly - unknown
    & How does neuronal activity bring about the interpretation of visual space in terms of objects or complex perceptual events? If they group, simple visual features can bring about the integration of spikes from neurons responding to different features to within a few milliseconds. Considered as a potential solution to the ‘‘binding problem,’’ it is suggested that neuronal synchronization is the glue for binding together different features of the same object. This idea receives some support from correlated- and periodic-stimulus motion (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  41
    Husserl and phenomenology.Sean D. Kelly - 2002 - In Robert C. Solomon & D. Sherman (eds.), Blackwell Guide to Continental Philosophy. Blackwell. pp. 12--112.
  22. What makes perceptual content non-conceptual?Sean D. Kelly - 2002 - Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy.
    the world. 1 Whereas the content of our beliefs, thoughts, and judgements necessarily involves "conceptualization" or "concept application", the content of our perceptual experiences is, according to Evans, "non-conceptual". Because Evans takes it for granted that we are often able to entertain thoughts about an object in virtue of having perceived it, a central problem in.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. Notes on Embodiment in Homer: Reading Homer on moods and action in the light of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty.Hubert L. Dreyfus & Sean D. Kelly - unknown
    Homer has a unique understanding of the body. On his view the body is that by means of which we are subject to moods, and moods are what attune us to our situation. Being attuned to a situation, in turn, opens us to the various ways things and people can be engaging. We agree with Homer that this receptivity is evident throughout our entire existence. It characterizes everything from our basic bodily skills for coping with objects and people to our (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Articles.Sean D. Kelly - unknown
    I begin by examining a recent debate between John McDowell and Christopher Peacocke over whether the content of perceptual experience is non-conceptual. Although I am sympathetic to Peacocke’s claim that perceptual content is non-conceptual, I suggest a number of ways in which his arguments fail to make that case. This failure stems from an over-emphasis on the “fine-grainedness” of perceptual content – a feature that is relatively unimportant to its non-conceptual structure. I go on to describe two other features of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Time and experience.Sean D. Kelly - forthcoming - In A. Brooks & Kathleen Akins (eds.), Philosophy and the Neurosciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  26. Bridging embodied cognition and brain function: The role of phenomenology.Donald Borrett, Sean D. Kelly & Hon Kwan - 2000 - Philosophical Psychology 13 (2):261-266.
    Both cognitive science and phenomenology accept the primacy of the organism-environment system and recognize that cognition should be understood in terms of an embodied agent situated in its environment. How embodiment is seen to shape our world, however, is fundamentally different in these two disciplines. Embodiment, as understood in cognitive science, reduces to a discussion of the consequences of having a body like ours interacting with our environment and the relationship is one of contingent causality. Embodiment, as understood phenomenologically, represents (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Essays in Honor of Hubert Dreyfus, Vol. II.Sean D. Kelly - 2000 - MIT Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. On time and truth.Sean D. Kelly - forthcoming - In Kurt J. Pritzl (ed.), Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy. Catholic University of America Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The Purpose of General Education.Sean D. Kelly - unknown
    I would like to begin by talking about General Education in America. General Education plays a very particular and interesting role in American Higher Education. A typical undergraduate at one of our colleges or universities is expected to satisfy a range of requirements in his or her major area of study (mathematics, economics, philosophy, etc.); and they will also take a range of electives – courses that are not required for graduation but in which the student might want to explore (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. What do we see (when we do)?Sean D. Kelly - 2007 - In Thomas Baldwin (ed.), Reading Merleau-Ponty: On Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. On the demonstration of blindsight in monkeys.Christopher Mole & Sean D. Kelly - 2006 - Mind and Language 21 (4):475-483.
    The work of Alan Cowey and Petra Stoerig is often taken to have shown that, following lesions analogous to those that cause blindsight in humans, there is blindsight in monkeys. The present paper reveals a problem in Cowey and Stoerig's case for blindsight in monkeys. The problem is that Cowey and Stoerig's results would only provide good evidence for blindsight if there is no difference between their two experimental paradigms with regard to the sorts of stimuli that are likely to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Content and constancy: Phenomenology, psychology, and the content of perception. [REVIEW]Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3):682–690.
  33. Reference and attention: A difficult connection. [REVIEW]Sean Dorrance Kelly - 2004 - Philosophical Studies 120 (1-3):277-86.
    I am very much in sympathy with the overall approach of John Campbell’s paper, “Reference as Attention”. My sympathy extends to a variety of its features. I think he is right to suppose, for instance, that neuropsychological cases provide important clues about how we should treat some traditional philosophical problems concerning perception and reference. I also think he is right to suppose that there are subtle but important relations between the phenomena of perception, action, consciousness, attention, and reference. I even (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34. Review of Andy Clark, Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again[REVIEW]Sean D. Kelly - 2000 - Mind 109 (433).
    The title of Andy Clark's book is, among other things, a reference to one of the central terms in Martin Heidegger's early work: "Dasein" (being there) is the word that Heidegger uses to refer to beings like ourselves. Clark is no Heidegger scholar, but the reference is deliberate; among the predecessors to his book he lists not only Heidegger himself, but also the American Heidegger scholar Hubert Dreyfus and the French Heideggerean phenomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty. This triumvirate has played an increasingly (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark